Skip to main content

Introduction to Real Number

Beyond real number, let's review some about rational number first. Rational number a.k.a the extension of natural number where we want to separate a integer.

Rational number

That's we define ration number as qQ,q=a/b,a,bN,b0\forall q\in \mathbb{Q}, q = a/b, a,b \in \N, b\ne 0

We would like to use decimal expansion to present rational number. But the interesting thing found here, we have many decimal expansions, how can we found the related one. For the finite decimal expansion, we just simply use 10n10^n where nn is the number of digits after dot to times such expansion then we have a integer, and now we can present it as a/ba/b so that all finite decimal expansions are rational. How about infinite decimal expansion? Some of them are eventually periodic, some of them are not. Among those expansion, how can we judge if it's a rational number?

Let's define the eventually periodic first. An infinite decimal x=a0.a1a2x = a0.a1a2\cdots is eventually periodic if there are positive integers nn and kk such that ai+k=aia_{i+k} = a_i for all i>ni > n.

  • let x=a0.a1a2x = a0.a1a2\ldots be arbitrary eventually periodic infinite decimal where n,kN,n0,iN,i>n    ai+k=ai\exists n,k\in \N, n \ge 0, \forall i \in \N, i > n \implies a_{i+k} = a_i
  • Since 10nx=a0an.an+110^{n} x = a_0\cdots a_n.a_{n+1}\ldots, 10n+kx=a0anan+k.an+k+110^{n+k} x = a_0\cdots a_n\cdots a_{n+k}. a_{n+k+1} \ldots and the decimals are the same (where n+1>nn+1 > n and ai=ai+k,i>na_i = a_{i+k}, \forall i > n) so that we will get a integer for 10n+kx10nx10^{n+k} x - 10^{n} x, and denote such integer as zz.
  • x(10n+k10n)=z    x=z10n+k10nx(10^{n+k} - 10^{n}) = z \implies x = \frac{z}{10^{n+k} - 10^{n}} where zNz\in \N and 10n+k10nN10^{n+k} - 10^{n} \in \N so that xx is a rational number.

As we can see the infinite periodic decimal expansion can be present as a/b,a,bN,b0a/b, a,b\in \N, b\ne 0, but we can't find a way to present the other that's why we have real number. Sometimes, we also said R\R is the extension of Q\mathbb{Q}

Let's look up how we extend it following!

Least Upper Bound Principle (& Greatest Lower Bound)

First, let's take R\R to describe some properties.

Let SS be a subset of real number SRS\subset\R be arbitrary

  • MR,sS,Ms    M\exists M\in \R, \forall s\in S, M \ge s \implies M is an upper bound for SS.
  • MR,sS,Ms    M\exists M\in \R, \forall s\in S, M \le s \implies M is an lower bound for SS
  • L,MR,s.t.sS,Ms,LsLM    L\exists L, \forall M \in R, s.t. \forall s\in S, M \ge s, L\ge s \land L \le M \iff L is the supremum (least upper bound) for SS. Denote supS=L\sup S = L
  • L,MR,s.t.sS,Ms,LsLM    L\exists L, \forall M \in R, s.t. \forall s\in S, M \le s, L\le s \land L \ge M \iff L is the infimum (greatest lower bound) for SS. Denote infS=L\inf S = L.
  • For ,inf=+,sup=\emptyset, \inf \emptyset = + \infty, \sup \emptyset = - \infty
  • When we say a set is bounded     \iff the set is both bounded above and bounded below.
  • Denote the maximum of SS as L, that's max(S)=L\max(S) = L. max(S)=L    supS=L\max(S) = L \implies \sup S = L. Similarly, Denote the minimum of SS as L, that's min(S)=L\min(S) = L. min(S)=L    infS=L\min(S) = L \implies \inf S = L.
    • Notice, supS=L\sup S = L does not imply such maximum exists. Similarly for infimum

Axios of Completeness: Every nonempty subset SS of R\R that is bounded above has a supremum. Similarly, every nonempty subset SS of R\R that is bounded below has an infimum.

Existence of R\R

Archimedean Property: (proved by Axios of Completeness)

  1. xR,nN,n>x\forall x\in \R, \exists n\in \N, n > x
  2. y>0R,nN,1n<y\forall y > 0 \in \R, \exists n\in \N, \frac{1}{n} < y

It seems all above already use R\R to present, it happends due to we can actually use those to all subset of R\R. Back to Q\mathbb{Q}, now we have following consequence of completeness:

Density of Q\mathbb{Q} in R\R: x,yR,s.t.x<y,rQ,s.t.x<r<y\forall x,y \in \R, s.t. x < y, \exists r \in \mathbb{Q}, s.t. x < r < y.

And furthermore, we can write:

  1. aR,a=sup{rQ:r<a}\forall a\in \R, a = \sup \{r \in \mathbb{Q}: r < a\}
  2. R={sup(A):AQ,A has upper bound in Q}\R = \{\sup(A): A \subseteq \mathbb{Q}, A \text{ has upper bound in } \mathbb{Q} \}
  3. NZQR\N \subset \Z \subset \mathbb{Q} \subset \R

All above show the existance of R\R is based on N,Z,Q\N, \Z, \mathbb{Q} by axiom of completeness, we need to know some definition before look at the proof.

We define an ordered pair (A,B)(A, B) of nonempty subsets of Q\mathbb{Q} as a Dedekind cut with properties:

  1. yA,x<y    xAy \in A, x < y \implies x \in A
  2. yB,x>y    xBy \in B, x > y \implies x \in B
  3. xA,yB,x<y\forall x \in A, \forall y \in B, x < y

Now look at the proof:

  1. Let aRa \in \R, let Aa={rQ:r<a}QA_a = \{r \in \mathbb{Q}: r < a\} \subseteq \mathbb{Q} is bounded by Q\mathbb{Q}, so that sup(Aa)=a\sup(A_a) = a.
  2. Let b=sup(Aa)b = \sup(A_a) by Axiom of Completeness, we have bRb \in \R.
  3. Assume aba \ne b, then a<ba < b
    1. Case 1: a<ba < b: since b=sup(Aa)b = \sup(A_a), then bab \le a which is a contradiction.
    2. Case 2: a>ba > b: rQ,b<r<a\exists r \in \mathbb{Q}, b < r < a by archimedean property, but b=sup(Aa)b = \sup(A_a) which is a contradiction.
  4. Thus, a=ba = b, so that aRa \in \R.

Since we know and prove how real number exists, let's look at a fundemental usage of real number αR,α2=2\exists \alpha \in \R, \alpha^2 = 2.

proof:

  1. Let A={xR:x2<2}A = \{x \in \R: x^2 < 2\}, AQ={xQ:x2>2}A_Q = \{x \in \mathbb{Q}: x^2 > 2\}. WTS A=AQ=2A=A_Q = \sqrt{2} which is equivalent to prove α=sup(A)    α2=2\alpha = \sup(A) \implies \alpha^2 = 2.
  2. We can prove the second one by contradiction, assume α22\alpha^2 \ne 2, then α2>2\alpha^2 > 2 or α2<2\alpha^2 < 2.
    1. Case 1: α2>2\alpha^2 > 2: nN,s.t.(α1n)2>2\exists n\in \N, s.t. (\alpha - \frac{1}{n})^2 > 2 by archimedean property, since α1n<αα=sup(A)    α1nA\alpha - \frac{1}{n} < \alpha \land \alpha = \sup(A) \implies \alpha - \frac{1}{n} \in A, then (α1n)2<x2<2(α1n)2>2(\alpha - \frac{1}{n})^2 < x^2 < 2 \land (\alpha - \frac{1}{n})^2 > 2 which is a contradiction.
    2. Case 2: α2<2\alpha^2 < 2: nN,s.t.1n<2α22α+1\exists n\in \N, s.t. \frac{1}{n} < \frac{2 - \alpha^2}{2\alpha + 1} by archimedean property, since α2<2    αA\alpha^2 < 2 \implies \alpha \in A, then (α+1n)2=α2+2αn+1n2<2α2+2α+1n<α2+2α2=2(\alpha + \frac{1}{n})^2 = \alpha^2 + \frac{2\alpha}{n} + \frac{1}{n^2} < 2 \le \alpha^2 + \frac{2\alpha + 1}{n} < \alpha^2 + 2 - \alpha^2 = 2 so that α+1nA\alpha + \frac{1}{n} \in A. Since α=sup(A),α+1nA\alpha = \sup(A), \alpha + \frac{1}{n} \notin A which is a contradiction.

Cardinality

We use the term cardinality to denote the number of elements in a set. If set AA has the same number of elements as set BB, we say AA and BB have the same cardinality. We denote ABA \sim B.

Formally, we define the cardinality of a set ABA \sim B if there is a bijection function between AA and BB.

Cantor Theorem: Q≁R\mathbb{Q} \not\sim \mathbb{R} and NZQ\N \sim \Z \sim \mathbb{Q}.

  • can prove by Schroeder-Bernstein Theorem
  • N2N\N^2 \sim \N then we can recursively apply this.

We define a set is finite if nN,s.t.X{1,2,,n}\exists n\in \N, s.t. X \sim \{1,2,\dots,n\}. But when we say countbale doesn't mean finite. We define a set is countable if XX is infinite and XNX \sim \N. And a set XX is uncountable if XX is infinite and X≁NX \not\sim \N.

Schroeder-Bernstein Theorem: XY    f:X1-1Y,g:Y1-1XX \sim Y \iff \exists f: X \overset{\text{1-1}}\to Y, \exists g: Y \overset{\text{1-1}}\to X

  • A sequence of countable sets is countable.

Since real number is a big set, we may find some special number in usage. We define rRr \in \R is algebraic if rr is a root of a polynomial with integer coefficients. And we can find that the set of algebraic number is countable. The set of non-algebraic number is dense in R\R.